The liberal tradition in politics is, first and
foremost, about individual liberty. Although its roots go far back in the
history of political thought, liberalism emerged as a distinct political theory
as a call for freedom of speech and of thought. As one eminent political
theorist observed, freedom of thought ‘is an idea which emerges slowly in the
West in the course of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries; and yet today,
in the eyes of the liberal, it is this liberty which is most precious of all’. Right
from the outset, the liberal case for freedom of conscience has derived from
devotion to human reason.
In Areopagitica: A Speech for the Liberty on
Unlicensed Printing (1644), John Milton argued for freedom of conscience and of
the press by appealing to reason and truth. ‘Truth’, Milton argued, is ‘our richest
Merchandise’. ‘Let her [i.e., truth] and Falsehood grapple; who ever knew truth
put to worse, in a free and open encounter?’ Given freedom of speech and
thought, truth will win out because, unlike superstition and error, which
varies from group to group and time to time, truth appeals to our universal,
shared, reason. Hence, proclaimed Milton, ‘Give me the liberty to know, to
utter, and to argue freely according to conscience, above all liberties’. Over
two hundred years later (1859), John Stuart Mill again appealed to truth and
reason in his case for freedom of thought and speech:
The beliefs which we have most warrant for,
have no safeguard to rest on, but a standing invitation to the whole world to
prove them unfounded. If the challenge is not accepted, or is accepted and the
attempt fails, we are far enough from certainty still; but we have done the
best that the existing state of human reason admits of; we have neglected
nothing that could give the truth a chance of reaching us: if the lists are
kept open, we may hope that if there be a better truth, it will be found when
the human mind is capable of receiving it; and in the meantime we may rely on
having attained such approach to truth, as is possible in our own day. This is
the amount of certainty attainable by a fallible being, and this the sole way
of attaining it.
Mill is struck by our fallibility: no matter how
much we have thought an issue through, we can never be certain that we are
correct – it is always possible we have fallen into error. Such fallible
creatures, Mill insists, can only suppose their beliefs approach the truth if
those beliefs are subject to criticism in free debate. Like Milton, Mill
believes that true opinions are more likely to be embraced in free discussion
because they appeal to our reason.
Milton and Mill advance classic statements of a
basic liberal theme: given freedom of thought, speech and inquiry, our common
human reason leads us toward increasing agreement on truths and rejection of falsehoods.
Sometimes this is put in terms of the ‘free marketplace of ideas’: in a free
competition of ideas, the truth will eventually win out, and the longer the
competition goes on, the more truths will be uncovered. Underlying this is the
conviction that while we are all subject to various sorts of biases,
superstitions, and errors, these differ from one person (or group) to another.
My biases and superstitions may appeal to me and some like-minded bigots, but
they are unlikely to gain universal acceptance because not everyone shares my
biases and superstitions. But, the liberal insists, the powers of reason are
shared and universal. Reason is what unites us. In the words of a
twentieth-century liberal, ‘[a]ll that man is and all that raises him above
animals he owes to his reason’. Overall reason selects the case for what is
true rather than what is false.
The exercise of our reason, then, leads us to
agree. Mill – and here he speaks for much of the liberal tradition – was thus
convinced that one aspect of social progress was convergence on an increasing
body of truths.
No comments:
Post a Comment